Explore
This article is from
Journal of Creation 31(2):103–109, August 2017

Browse our latest digital issue Subscribe

Carol Cleland’s case for historical science—part 1: devaluing experimental science

by and

Before uniformitarian geology derailed biblical history, the rails were greased by an unwarranted confidence in scientific history. What is the relationship between science, history, and truth? Carol Cleland, a leading philosopher of science, attempts an answer. Reacting to critics who claim historical science is less valid than experimental science, she defends their epistemic equality with both negative and positive arguments. Her negative argument highlights flaws in both the theory and practice of experimental science. Although her arguments ably undermine some modern distortions, her case against experimental science in this paper relies on the straw man of positivism—the idea that science is the arbiter of truth—and is thus less robust than a traditional Christian understanding of the relationship between science and revelation.


Carol Cleland points out limits and weaknesses of experimental science, but misses the biblical foundation needed for both science and history.

Clelands--argument
Figure 1. A map of Cleland’s argument for epistemic equality of historical and experimental science. This paper focuses on the negative case against experimental science.

Carol Cleland and historical science

Geology has begun to interest philosophers of science. This is notable; for many years, philosophers saw physics as the prototypical science and left philosophizing about geology to geologists (e.g. G.G. Simpson, S.J. Gould). But in recent years, increasing numbers of philosophers have been drawn to geology, to the extent that they authored the first three papers of the 2013 Geological Society of America’s Rethinking the Fabric of Geology.1 One is Dr Carol Cleland of the University of Colorado, who has built a strong reputation on her defence of historical science as able to guarantee similar levels of epistemic confidence as experimental science.2–6 She has been a consistent advocate for historical science during a time when the optimistic positivism of the 19th and 20th centuries has been deflated.

Cleland is correct to prick the pretension of scientists. Positivism has long sold a false confidence in science. Cleland agrees that experimental science is powerful, but argues that it is not a unique path to truth, nor even unique as ‘science’.7

Cleland’s negative case: experimental science is flawed

Cleland focuses on emphasizing the validity of historical science as a separate science, rather than addressing the root problem of naturalism. Her goal is straightforward:

“I argue that while it is true that there are fundamental differences in methodology between the historical natural sciences and classical experimental sciences, it is a mistake to conclude that the scientific status of the former is inferior to that of the latter.”8

Her pursuit of that goal follows two paths (figure 1). The first is a negative critique of experimental science, seeking to deflate its perceived superiority. Following her outline, we first examine her negative case. Her argument for this case is twofold—theoretical and practical weaknesses inherent to experimental science limit its epistemic value.

Theoretical weaknesses

Though Cleland directs her attack at experimental science, her critique would be more accurately seen as one on the secular distortion of positivism, showing weaknesses in the prevailing secular attitude about science, not science per se. Positivism has probably passed its zenith as an intellectual idea, but it remains strong as an emotive attitude:

“The essential point of that doctrine is simply the affirmation of science, and the denial of philosophy and religion.”9

This attitude twists science; it grants to modern science the position occupied by the Bible in earlier generations. As the pinnacle of truth, science breeds an accompanying arrogance, which animates the dismissive attitude of Henry Gee, a senior editor of Nature and Cleland’s foil:

“Taking aim at all historiographic research, Gee writes, ‘they [historiographic hypotheses] can never be tested by experiment, and so they are unscientific … . No science can ever be historical’ … . For Gee and fellow travelers a genuine test of a hypothesis requires experimentation. Historiographic hypotheses cannot be tested in this manner. Hence, they are unscientific.”10

Cleland attacks that position with a philosophical jujitsu that highlights theoretical and practical flaws. She starts slowly, by drawing a line between practitioners and philosophers of science:

“Many scientists and most laypersons are still enthralled by this conception of science as a fundamentally experimental enterprise, which helps to explain some of the trenchant criticisms mounted against scientific historiography. However, this view is no longer popular among philosophers of science.”10

Whether or not a view is popular among philosophers of science says little of its validity, nor should it be assumed that philosophers of science, as such, have a mystic insight into truth denied to ‘scientists and most laypersons’. But she moves to a firmer footing by noting the major theoretical weakness of induction, ironically traced back to David Hume—an early and enthusiastic secularist:

“Unfortunately such inductivism faces David Hume’s … intractable problems of induction: No finite body of evidence, however varied and extensive, can conclusively establish the truth of a universal generalization applying to unobserved as well as observed cases.”11

She illustrates Hume’s argument by noting that everyone once thought that ‘all swans are white’, until black swans were discovered in Australia.

For centuries, science sought to discover truth by testing and confirming hypotheses using what Adler termed special experience:

“… experience we have as the result of investigative efforts on our part, and only as the results of such efforts [emphasis in original].”12

Confirmation, though tentative, happened when positive affirmations of hypotheses were made by controlled observation. Early science avoided Hume’s trap because scientists did not demand absolute truth from their work; that was the task of theology, freeing science to discover valid, piecemeal truths without having to deductively justify each conclusion.13 Science was tentative; new information provided new insight. But when secularists sought to replace theology with science (as Hume advocated at the end of An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding), science had to assume that burden. Unfortunately, it took some time for the implication of Hume’s new view of science to penetrate the Enlightenment euphoria.

Eventually, scientists realized that finding positive affirmations of hypotheses (which Cleland calls ‘justificationism’) could not prove them:

“… justificationists argue that while hypotheses cannot be conclusively proven, their probability can nonetheless be raised by enough successful predictions. Unfortunately, theories of justificationism face the probabilistic version of the hoary problem of induction.”14

To ‘rescue’ science, Karl Popper15 proposed falsifying, instead of justifying, hypotheses. Hypotheses that survived rigorous testing were considered true. But that solution still does not meet Cleland’s standard:

“Philosophers have known for more than half a century that falsificationism is deeply flawed logically. Falsificationism treats hypotheses as if they were being tested in isolation from nature—as if a prediction involves no assumptions about boundary or initial conditions of the hypothesis. But … hypotheses and theories never stand alone when tested in real-word scenarios. Whether conducted in a lab or the field, a concrete test of a hypothesis involves an enormous number of auxiliary assumptions … about instrumentation, pertinent conditions, and the absence of potentially interfering factors, many of which are highly theoretical, poorly understood, or simply unknown.”16

In other words, scientists are finite and fallible and must rely on assumptions to conduct experimental or historical science. Popper’s view is still popular in some circles, but Cleland is correct in noting that neither justificationism nor falsificationism guarantees the epistemic expectations of autonomous science:

“In summary, traditional accounts of the scientific method (justificationism and falsificationism) are logically flawed and moreover do not provide faithful reconstructions of the evidential reasoning of either experimental or historical scientists. It follows that appeals to the ‘scientific method’ cannot be used to undermine the scientific status of the historical sciences.”16

Cleland seems to believe that she has won a great victory for historical science, by showing that both kinds of science are equally wrong. Instead of turning to Christianity to rescue truth, scholars prefer to cut off their nose to spite their face.

One of the most interesting implications of Cleland’s argument is that the method of science is not singular:

“In addition, the dogmatic view that the success of science must be attributable to some as yet unspecified universal scientific method for which experimental science provides the prototype, is undermined by studies showing that even experimental scientists employ a variety of different methods in their research practice.”17

She later argues that a single scientific method is unrealistic. Instead, each ‘kind’ of science should have its own method:

“In the first place … many doubts about the scientific status of historical research are rooted in a one-size-fits-all account of the methodology of science that is deeply flawed, both logically and as an account of the actual practices of scientists (including experimentalists).”18

If this is true, how is ‘science’ defined? Is it a meaningless ‘feel-good’ qualifier? Dimly perceiving this problem, Cleland insists that it retains an essential unity by virtue of the same goal—relating hypotheses to explanations and predictions via empirical evidence. In that sense:

“Most historiographic hypotheses are supported or ‘confirmed’ by evidence in virtue of the power of the hypothesis to explain (vs predict) the evidence.”19

The process is not as neat in historical science as it is in experimental science because:

“Experience suggests, however, that if there are regularities relating particular evidential traces to their long past causes they are extremely messy and rough, riddled with exceptions and contingencies, and thus not at all like the stereotypical laws of physics.”20

She brushes aside these problems as the price of doing business, admitting that scientists like Gee may have a small case if their understanding of historical science is correct:

“The central problem with narrative accounts of scientific historiographic explanation is the stress placed upon formulating a coherent story over empirically validating it … . This conflicts with the traditional emphasis in natural science on evidential warrant. … If the main reason for accepting a historiographic hypothesis is its explanatory power and it draws its explanatory power primarily from the coherence and continuity of a quasi-fictional story, then scientific historiography really does seem inferior to experimental science.”21

She insists, however, that this is not a problem because science is not about an experimental method, but:

“… the central focus of historians of nature is on securing empirically well-founded connections between evidence and hypothesis … they emphasize more direct inferential strategies for inferring long past common causes from present-day effects.”22

Thus, it is not the traditional scientific method that defines ‘science’, but the ability to empirically establish links between hypotheses and evidence. In her view, experimental science does that in terms of prediction; historical science does it in terms of retrodiction. At root, Cleland insists that scientists of all stripes are simply linking empirical evidence to hypothesis:

“I conclude that the putatively problematic differences in research strategies between historical scientists and experimentalists reflect pervasive causal differences in their evidential situations; the methodology of each domain is designed to accommodate and exploit causal, as well as logical characteristics of the evidential relation between hypothesis and observation. The view that historical science is somehow inferior to experimental science is based upon a mistaken account of scientific methodology that reconstructs scientific reasoning entirely in terms of purely formal, logico-mathematical considerations.”14

Practical weaknesses

After highlighting some theoretical weaknesses of experimental science, making assertions that historical and experimental science have distinct methods, and redefining ‘science’ as ‘linking evidence to hypothesis’, she proceeds to the second aspect of her argument—experimental science also fails in practice. She leans heavily on Kuhn:23

“The ‘logic’ of the methodology of science was not the only victim of post-positivist critiques of science. Hanson … and Kuhn … attacked the idea that observation, however carefully conducted, is unbiased, establishing that all evidence is irrevocably contaminated by theory; in order to count as evidence, observations must be interpreted and interpretation inevitably utilizes theoretical concepts and assumptions. … In short, experimental science had failed to live up to its early promise as a model for all science.”24

In other words, scientists are not AI (artificial intelligence) truth machines. We all know that scientists are fallible, not always virtuous, and driven by paradigmatic commitments stemming from their worldview, their politics, greed, or passion. Her insight is valid, but early scientists (thanks to Christianity) understood human nature better than moral relativists. They were realists, expecting man’s fallen nature to produce ‘better’, not ‘perfect’, because that was for the next world.25 But as secularists like Hume displaced Christianity with mathematics and science, and later optimists preached science as a panacea for perfectible humans, the early ethical framework began to crumble. Events have shown its failure and illustrated the truth of Christian doctrine—men cannot attain perfect behaviour any more than they can attain perfect truth.

Early modernists spent the accrued Christian capital, not realizing it was vanishing. Dostoevsky wrote: “If God does not exist, then everything is permitted”, and scientists are no less exempt from the moral consequences of atheism. Postmodern man is learning that while being the lone atheist in a tolerant, ethical society may be fun, ruling in one of evil and despair is not. Kuhn highlighted relatively minor issues of fallibility; recent events would shock him. We see the political corruption of science,26,27 and the persecution of dissidents in academia is now reaching politically incorrect secularists as well as Christians.28,29 We are even seeing falsified research results.30 Today’s science needs Christian ethics as well as Christian truth.

So Cleland correctly notes that the theory and practice of science cannot bear the weight of absolute truth. Science minimizes the unknowns and maximizes confidence, but confidence in its results and truth was historically undergirded by faith in the absolute truth of revelation and in man’s ability to comprehend it. Secular man is finally seeing that science’s biblical foundation was not displaced without consequences.

In light of these problems, can the status of historical science be advanced by devaluing experimental science? If ‘justificationism’ fails the test of induction and ‘falsificationism’ does not account for all of the variables in the equation, then science, doomed to uncertainty, certainly has no room for the arrogance of positivism. In Cleland’s opinion, comments by those like Henry Gee are the pot calling the kettle black.

Discussion

Renewed assessments of historical science, whether from philosophers or scientists, should prove beneficial to a brand mired in early 19th century positivism. As such, Cleland’s work is a welcome contrast to the ideological ideas of the mid-20th century. But her work also highlights the failure of Christians to retake this valuable ground.

interpretive-forensic-models
Figure 2. In Christianity, interpretive forensic models are constructed from data shaped by forensic paradigms, which in turn are shaped by philosophical and theological assumptions. For that reason, an epistemological hierarchy is affirmed. Positions are determined by any step’s need for presupposition supplied by another. Metaphysical truth presupposes revelation, defining their relative positions. Forensic models of Earth history occupy the end of a hierarchical chain, depending on a chain of presuppositions.

Many orthodox Christian ideas seem archaic to the postmodern generation. For example, the foundational nature of special revelation to any human truth seems preposterous, because ‘everyone’ knows truth is relative. It is hard then to acknowledge that human knowledge is epistemically inferior to God’s simply because humans are metaphysically inferior to God. The epistemological hierarchy inherent in Christianity (figure 2) has been forgotten. Positivism has been unable to provide a viable substitute, and epistemological egalitarianism contributes to the confusion Cleland seeks to dispel. To make things worse, postmodernists cling to positivism, but as a presupposition, not an intellectual proposition. Thus, they continue to conflate science and history, just as Cleland does.

Cleland raises an immediate red flag in her decision to critique experimental science. Why not simply present a positive case for historical science? Why diminish another discipline? It seems uncomfortably like an emotive appeal to those victimized by the unbridled arrogance of secular scientists. Truth, not equality, should be the objective.

Her negative case exhibits several problems. First and foremost, most of her arguments against experimental science also apply to historical science. Are experimental scientists unable to overcome Hume’s challenge? Historical scientists rely on induction too. Are experimental scientists prone to ignorance, error, bias, dishonesty, greed, or pettiness? Historical scientists are people too. Do unknown or uncontrolled variables preclude absolute certainty in experimental science? Historical science is worse—its uncertainties are much greater, and cannot be reduced by controlled, repetitive experiments. At root, her fundamental error is building a straw man of science as the arbiter of truth.

Adlers-classification-lge
Figure 3. Adler’s classification of disciplines based on the dual dichotomies of empirical vs formal and investigative vs non-investigative. Science is more than just ‘empirical’ and is distinguished from other empirical disciplines by its objects of inquiry, which are questions about universal principles of nature.

Furthermore, her ‘epistemic competition’ between experimental and historical science misses the point. Why do all empirical disciplines have to be ‘science’? This is a category error; science is a part of empirical knowledge, not its sum (figure 3). Adler’s31 classification of natural history as a ‘mixed question’—in which philosophy, science, history, theology, and revelation all play a part—is a better description both in theory and in practice.32 That subtlety of an inherent positivism has led us to reject the ‘origin/ operation’ model; it repeats this error by labelling origins, history, and even the supernormal, as ‘science’. This view also denigrates history, which is a valid empirical discipline that does not need the appellation ‘science’. Modernists are like a compass needle; they always point to science for validation. Today, history sells its noble tradition for whatever crumbs science deigns to toss its way.33,34

Christian-response
Figure 4. Christian response to Cleland’s negative case. Her points are valid when applied to positivism, but much less so in the context of the Christian worldview.

What about her case against experimental science due to its practical problems? She references those described by Kuhn in the 1960s. We believe they are more problematic today because of inroads made by relativist views about truth and ethics. Apart from God, scientists cannot maintain a consistent intellectual and ethical framework for science. Their practice puts the lie to both. Worse, the coming wave of nihilists won’t do science; they will only scavenge its technology. Cleland admits that secular scientists have professional shortcomings, but is not curious about the reasons. Christianity could answer her questions; both epistemological and ethical (figure 4). Cleland is trapped in the world of positivism. This is the major weakness of her case (figure 1).

One way to understand the difference between answers from Christianity and naturalism was described by Adler. He drew a distinction between the absolute truth of epistēmē and the contingent, partial, and evolving knowledge of doxa. Science belongs to the latter. He looked beyond the binary option of ‘knowledge’ vs ‘opinion’ to a trinity of options: (1) private (subjective) opinion, (2) public (objective) opinion, and (3) certain truth (figure 5). Science, like any other valid discipline, provides predominantly public opinion that ranges along a scale of certainty. Error is therefore not catastrophic, because the truths affirmed are largely contingent.

In that construct, Hume’s argument is not fatal, because science does not carry the burden of epistēmē. God’s truth undergirds human knowledge. It also provides the ethical framework needed for science, including the inherent value of people created in God’s image. In all these ways, it validates the presuppositions of science, supports its methods, and ethically regulates its practitioners. It does the same for history and any other valid discipline. Differences are not measured in epistemological superiority or inferiority, but by the subjects, questions, and methods each uses. Science may have an advantage in its own domain, but ultimately the contingent truths of any discipline are measured against the absolute truth of God’s knowledge, not each other.

episteme
Figure 5. Instead of a binary division between opinion and knowledge (A), Adler recognized a distinction between private and public opinion (B). Public opinion, doxa, can increase in certainty along a scale of increasing logical validity and increasing empirical confirmation. Absolute knowledge, epistēmē, is the limited set of indubitable truth. If science is not epistēmē, then Cleland’s critique loses much of its urgency.

The creation trials of the 1980s forced both Christians and secularists to question the reigning positivist view of science. The cases turned on distinguishing ‘science’ from ‘religion’. Although the judges assigned secular geohistory and biohistory to ‘science’, and creationism to ‘religion’, their confidence was not shared by some philosophers. Laudan35 questioned the demarcation criteria assumed during the trials. By 1992, Bauer was questioning whether there was such a thing as the ‘scientific method’.36

Christians belatedly addressed these questions, but did not reassert the uniquely Christian foundations of science. Instead they looked for a resolution within positivism, typically inventing multiple kinds of science.37–39 Others ignored the question:

“… most contemporary philosophers of science regard the question, ‘What methods distinguish science from nonscience?’ as both intractable and uninteresting.”40

But creationists should address the nature and practice of science. Liberating it from both modernist positivism and postmodernist relativism can only be done by Christianity.

Cleland’s main failing is having no foundation for unified, absolute truth. Empiricism demands the possibility of ongoing revision. Creationists are best placed to see the damage to science and history caused by modernism41 and postmodernism.42,43 Biblical Christianity created the intellectual conditions for science, and only biblical Christianity can save science, since science cannot survive the collapse of normative truth and ethics. The challenge for creationists has moved from justifying biblical history to rescuing both science and history from the abyss of relativistic views of truth and ethics. The damage is already great; recent decades have seen an accelerating subordination of truth to ideology—most obvious in the climate wars—and that loss of truth (and derivative ethics) echoes through science:

“It is simply no longer possible to believe much of the clinical research that is published, or to rely on the judgment of trusted physicians or authoritative medical guidelines. I take no pleasure in this conclusion, which I reached slowly and reluctantly over my two decades as an editor of the New England Journal of Medicine.”44

Conclusion

Secularists and Christians alike are confused about the nature of science, thanks to years of distortion. Both appear to approve of multiple kinds of science, although that raises the question of which kinds are more ‘scientific’ than others. Cleland attempts to justify the equality of experimental and historical science by first pointing to theoretical and practical problems with experimental science as an indication that their perceived superiority is misplaced. But her negative case depends on several assumptions. The first is the category error of conflating empiricism and science, which shows up as defining ‘science’ as nothing more than empirically linking hypotheses to evidence. The second is the presuppositional error of positivism, which places a burden on science (of any kind) that cannot be borne. Experimental science and natural history are epistemic equals only in the sense that both are unique, empirical disciplines able to find truth within the Christian worldview. They are not epistemic equals in the sense of certainty, because the experimental method allows a reduction in subjective elements that the forensic methods of natural history do not.

Christians have been heavily influenced by positivism and fall prey to the same trap. Geisler,37 Geisler and Anderson,38 and Thaxton et al.39 illustrated this with their scheme of expanding science to include: ‘operation science’, ‘historical science’, ‘origin science’, and ‘supranormal science’, which perpetuated positivism. Creationists often abridge this idea to the dualistic ‘origins’ and ‘operations’ science. But language is always critical to thought, and so we encourage more careful use of language and the re-evaluation of both science and history within the worldview of the Bible.

Posted on homepage: 23 November 2018

References and notes

  1. Baker, V.R. (Ed.), Rethinking the Fabric of Geology, Geological Society of America Special Paper 502, Boulder, CO, 2013. Return to text.
  2. Cleland, C.E., Historical science, experimental science, and the scientific method, Geology 29(11):987–990, 2001. Return to text.
  3. Cleland, C.E., Methodological and epistemic differences between historical science and experimental science, Philosophy of Science 69:474–496, 2002. Return to text.
  4. Cleland, C.E., Philosophical issues in natural history and its historiography; in: Tucker, A. (Ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of History and Historiography, John Wiley & Sons, Chichester, UK, pp. 44–62, 2011. Return to text.
  5. Cleland, C.E., Prediction and explanation in historical natural science, British J. Philosophy of Science 62:551–582, 2011. Return to text.
  6. Cleland, C.E., Common cause explanation and the search for the ‘smoking gun’, in: Baker, ref. 1, pp. 1–10. Return to text.
  7. As an aside, there is irony in Cleland’s case. Charles Lyell caught a 19th century wave of scientific euphoria, and built uniformitarian natural history as an extension of Newton’s physics, linking the two through his deceptive ‘uniformity principle’. He succeeded in riding Newton’s coat-tails to an exalted height. Now that the positivist wave is receding, Cleland advances a high view of geology by denigrating physics! See Laudan, R., From Mineralogy to Geology: The foundations of a science, 1650–1830, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, 1987. Return to text.
  8. Cleland, ref. 6, p. 1. Return to text.
  9. Adler, M.J., A Second Look in the Rearview Mirror, Macmillan, New York, pp. 31–32, 1992. Return to text.
  10. Cleland, ref. 4, p. 45, brackets hers. Return to text.
  11. Cleland, ref. 4, p. 47. Return to text.
  12. Adler, M.J., The Conditions of Philosophy, Athenaeum Press, New York, p. 102, 1965. Return to text.
  13. Glover, W., Biblical Origins of Modern Secular Culture, Mercer University Press, Macon, GA, 1984. Return to text.
  14. Cleland, ref. 6, p. 2. Return to text.
  15. Popper, K., Conjectures and Refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge, 2nd edn, Harper & Row, New York, 1965. Return to text.
  16. Cleland, ref. 6, p. 3. Return to text.
  17. Cleland, ref. 4, p. 49. Return to text.
  18. Cleland, ref. 6, pp. 1–2. Return to text.
  19. Cleland, ref. 4, p. 51. Return to text.
  20. Cleland, ref. 4, p. 52. Return to text.
  21. Cleland, ref. 4, p. 54. Return to text.
  22. Cleland, ref. 4, p. 55. Return to text.
  23. Kuhn, T., The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, 1962. Return to text.
  24. Cleland, ref. 4, p. 46. Return to text.
  25. Harrison, P., The Fall of Man and the Foundations of Science, Cambridge University Press, 2007; reviewed by Weinberger, L., J. Creation 24(3):18–21, 2010. Return to text.
  26. Horton, R., Offline: what is medical’s 5 sigma? The Lancet 385(9976):1380, 2015 | DOI: 10.1016/S0140-6736(15)60696-1. Return to text.
  27. Moran, A. (Ed.), Climate Change: The facts, Stockade Books, Woodsville, NH, 2015. Return to text.
  28. Bergman, J., Slaughter of the Dissidents, Leafcutter Press, Green Forest, AR, 2008. Return to text.
  29. Ghosh, P., UCL says Tim Hunt will not be back after ‘sexist’ comments, bbc.com, 26 June 2015. Return to text.
  30. The Economist, How science goes wrong, economist.com, 21 October 2013. Return to text.
  31. Adler, ref. 12, p. 303. Return to text.
  32. Reed, J.K. and Klevberg, P., Beyond “origin and operation” science, part II: an alternative, Creation Research Society Quarterly 51(1):31–39, 2014. Return to text.
  33. Clark, G.H., Historiography: Secular and religious, The Trinity Foundation, Jefferson, MD, 1994. Return to text.
  34. Reed, J.K., Historiography and natural history, Creation Research Society Quarterly 37(3):160–175, 1999. Return to text.
  35. Laudan, L., The demise of the demarcation problem; in: Cohen, R.S. and Laudan, L. (Eds.), Physics, Philosophy, and Psychoanalysis, Reidel, Dordrecht, 1983; reprinted in But Is It Science? Prometheus Books, New York, pp. 337–350, 1996. Return to text.
  36. Bauer, H.H., Scientific Literacy and the Myth of the Scientific Method, Illini Books, Urbana-Champaign, IL,1992. Return to text.
  37. Geisler, N.L., Is Man the Measure? An evaluation of contemporary humanism, Baker Book House, Grand Rapids, MI, 1983. Return to text.
  38. Geisler, N.L. and Anderson, J.K., Origin Science: A proposal for the creation-evolution controversy, Baker Book House, Grand Rapids, MI, 1987. Return to text.
  39. Thaxton, C.B., Bradley, W.L., and Olsen, R.L., The Mystery of Life’s Origin: Reassessing current theories, Philosophical Library, New York, 1984. Return to text.
  40. Meyer, S.C., The demarcation of science and religion, discovery.org, 2000. Return to text.
  41. The Enlightenment to 20th century attitude of optimism in scientific truth as the foundation of a new secular culture. Return to text.
  42. The recent (mid-20th century onwards) attitude of pessimism based on no absolutes in truth, ethics, or human hope. Return to text.
  43. Rose, E. (Fr Seraphim), Nihilism: The root of the revolution of the modern age, St. Herman Press, Platina, CA, 2009. Return to text.
  44. Angell, M., Drug companies and doctors: a story of corruption, New York Review of Books, nybooks.com, 15 January 2009. Return to text.

Helpful Resources

Rocks Aren't Clocks
by John K Reed
US $15.00
Soft cover
How Noah's Flood Shaped Our Earth
by Michael J Oard, John K Reed
US $17.00
Soft cover
Evolution's Achilles' Heels
by Nine Ph.D. scientists
US $17.00
Soft cover